Kant thinks of laws of nature as descriptive, universal and deterministic; e.g., Boyle's Law. The phrase "Laws of freedom" sounds self-contradictory. But for Kant, freedom entails neither license nor arbitrary choice, so it, too, will exhibit lawfulness. Although universal, any laws of freedom will turn out to be radically unlike laws of nature by being prescriptive and non-deterministic. How such laws are possible poses, for Kant, deep and difficult problems. These problems aren't addressed until the end of Section II and Section III. The problem of freedom is also discussed in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason and his Critique of Practical Reason
Logic consists of purely formal laws; e.g., if p then q, not-q, so not-p (modus tollens). These laws have a necessity that cannot be provided by experience. The natural sciences and ethics, however, are not entirely formal. While the principle that "every event has a cause" is synthetic yet known a priori --and hence is not based on experience--the specific content of the natural sciences is derived from experience; e.g., that smoking causes lung cancer. The empirical part of ethics includes what we now call psychology and the social sciences. These are important because they tell us what kinds of challenges we face as we think and judge what we are to do. Whatever laws either the natural or the social sciences confirm, however, has only a limited bearing on morality. Clearly, if you had been pushed off the top of the Empire State Building, you will "obey" the law of freely falling bodies. As you cannot do otherwise, it would be fatuous to tell you that you "ought" to fall faster or slower or not at all. But Kant does not believe that psychological or sociological laws eliminate freedom and responsibility. So a law stating that everyone breaks promises from time to time is, strictly speaking, irrelevant to any deliberation about what I ought to do or whether I'm culpable for any lies I tell.
In his Critique of Pure Reason Kant argues that speculative metaphysics makes extravagant claims leading to antinomies; i.e., we can demonstrate both a thesis and its denial by impeccable arguments. Metaphysics, however, need not be speculative: it can be critical. It can, that is, seek to discover those Intuitions (of space and time) and Categories (e.g., substance, causality) without which we cannot make sense of experience. Consider our judgment that every event has a cause. Because it is not merely definitional, it is not analytic; it is synthetic in that it connects two things separable in thought. As it is a synthetic we cannot demonstrate its truth by pure logic, as speculative metaphysicians try to do. Nor, as David Hume shows, can we derive that judgment from experience. Hume's conclusion raises the spectre of skepticism. Fortunately, we can acquire justified a priori knowledge of this judgment because of its role in making experience possible for us: the judgment is both universal and strictly necessary. Establishing the validity of such principles is part of pure philosophy, though not pure formal philosophy (which is formal logic as we know it).
That part of science that considers and establishes certain pure, categorical principles of experience Kant calls a metaphysics of nature. As we've seen, such a metaphysics will be critical, not speculative. The aim of the Grundlegung is to determine whether a metaphysics of morals is possible. If it is, then we should be able to uncover one or more fundamental laws of freedom that determines how we are to act in a way analogous (but not identical) to the way the judgment that every event has a cause determines how we order the world as experienced.